How do I use the Church encoding for Free Monads?
Asked Answered
A

4

11

I've been using the Free datatype in Control.Monad.Free from the free package. Now I'm trying to convert it to use F in Control.Monad.Free.Church but can't figure out how to map the functions.

For example, a simple pattern matching function using Free would look like this -

-- Pattern match Free
matchFree
  :: (a -> r)
  -> (f (Free f a) -> r)
  -> Free f a
  -> r
matchFree kp _ (Pure a) = kp a
matchFree _ kf (Free f) = kf f

I can easily convert it to a function that uses F by converting to/from Free -

-- Pattern match F (using toF and fromF)
matchF
  :: Functor f
  => (a -> r)
  -> (f (F f a) -> r)
  -> F f a
  -> r
matchF kp kf = matchF' . fromF
  where
    matchF' (Pure a) = kp a
    matchF' (Free f) = kf (fmap toF f)

However I can't figure out how to get it done without using toF and fromF -

-- Pattern match F (without using toF)???
-- Doesn't compile
matchF
  :: Functor f
  => (a -> r)
  -> (f (F f a) -> r)
  -> F f a
  -> r
matchF kp kf f = f kp kf

There must be a general pattern I am missing. Can you help me figure it out?

Arillode answered 14/7, 2015 at 5:45 Comment(0)
R
10

You asked for the "general pattern you are missing". Let me give my own attempt at explaining it, though Petr Pudlák's answer is also pretty good. As user3237465 says, there are two encodings that we can use, Church and Scott, and you're using Scott rather than Church. So here's the general review.

How encodings work

By continuation passing, we can describe any value of type x by some unique function of type

data Identity x = Id { runId :: x } 
{- ~ - equivalent to - ~ -} 
newtype IdentityFn x = IdFn { runIdFn ::  forall z. (x -> z) -> z }

The "forall" here is very important, it says that this type leaves z as an unspecified parameter. The bijection is that Id . ($ id) . runIdFn goes from IdentityFn to Identity while IdFn . flip ($) . runId goes the other way. The equivalence comes because there is essentially nothing one can do with the type forall z. z, no manipulations are sufficiently universal. We can equivalently state that newtype UnitFn = UnitFn { runUnitFn :: forall z. z -> z } has only one element, namely UnitFn id, which means that it corresponds to the unit type data Unit = Unit in a similar way.

Now the currying observation that (x, y) -> z is isomorphic to x -> y -> z is the tip of a continuation-passing iceberg which allows us to represent data structures in terms of pure functions, with no data structures, because clearly the type Identity (x, y) is equivalent therefore to forall z. (x -> y -> z) -> z. So "gluing" together two items is the same as creating a value of this type, which just uses pure functions as "glue".

To see this equivalence, we have to just handle two other properties.

The first is sum-type constructors, in the form of Either x y -> z. See, Either x y -> z is isomorphic to

newtype EitherFn x y = EitherFn { runEitherFn :: forall z. (x -> z) -> (y -> z) -> z }

from which we get the basic idea of the pattern:

  1. Take a fresh type variable z that does not appear in the body of the expression.
  2. For each constructor of the data type, create a function-type which takes all of its type-arguments as parameters, and returns a z. Call these "handlers" corresponding to the constructors. So the handler for (x, y) is (x, y) -> z which we curry to x -> y -> z, and the handlers for Left x | Right y are x -> z and y -> z. If there are no parameters, you can just take a value z as your function rather than the more cumbersome () -> z.
  3. Take all of those handlers as parameters to an expression forall z. Handler1 -> Handler2 -> ... -> HandlerN -> z.
  4. One half of the isomorphism is basically just to hand the constructors in as the desired handlers; the other pattern-matches on the constructors and applies the correponding handlers.

Subtle missing things

Again, it's fun to apply these rules to various things; for example as I noted above, if you apply this to data Unit = Unit you find that any unit type is the identity function forall z. z -> z, and if you apply this to data Bool = False | True you find the logic functions forall z. z -> z -> z where false = const while true = const id. But if you do play with it you will notice that something's missing still. Hint: if we look at

data List x = Nil | Cons x (List x)

we see that the pattern should look like:

data ListFn x = ListFn { runListFn :: forall z. z -> (x -> ??? -> z) -> z }

for some ???. The above rules don't pin down what goes there.

There are two good options: either we use the power of the newtype to its fullest to put ListFn x there (the "Scott" encoding), or we can preemptively reduce it with the functions we've been given, in which case it becomes a z using the functions that we already have (the "Church" encoding). Now since the recursion is already being performed for us up-front, the Church encoding is only perfectly equivalent for finite data structures; the Scott encoding can handle infinite lists and such. It can also be hard to understand how to encode mutual recursion in the Church form whereas the Scott form is usually a little more straightforward.

Anyway, the Church encoding is a little harder to think about, but a little more magical because we get to approach it with wishful thinking: "assume that this z is already whatever you're trying to accomplish with tail list, then combine it with head list in the appropriate way." And this wishful thinking is precisely why people have trouble understanding foldr, as the one side of this bijection is precisely the foldr of the list.

There are some other problems like "what if, like Int or Integer, the number of constructors is big or infinite?". The answer to this particular question is to use the functions

data IntFn = IntFn { runIntFn :: forall z. (z -> z) -> z -> z }

What is this, you ask? Well, a smart person (Church) has worked out that this is a way to represent integers as the repetition of composition:

zero f x = x
one f x = f x
two f x = f (f x)
{- ~ - increment an `n` to `n + 1` - ~ -}
succ n f = f . n f

Actually on this account m . n is the product of the two. But I mention this because it is not too hard to insert a () and flip arguments around to find that this is actually forall z. z -> (() -> z -> z) -> z which is the list type [()], with values given by length and addition given by ++ and multiplication given by >>.

For greater efficiency, you might Church-encode data PosNeg x = Neg x | Zero | Pos x and use the Church encoding (keeping it finite!) of [Bool] to form the Church encoding of PosNeg [Bool] where each [Bool] implicitly ends with an unstated True at its most-significant bit at the end, so that [Bool] represents the numbers from +1 to infinity.

An extended example: BinLeaf / BL

One more nontrivial example, we might think about the binary tree which stores all of its information in leaves, but also contains annotations on the internal nodes: data BinLeaf a x = Leaf x | Bin a (BinLeaf a x) (BinLeaf a x). Following the recipe for Church encoding we do:

newtype BL a x = BL { runBL :: forall z. (x -> z) -> (a -> z -> z -> z) -> z}

Now instead of Bin "Hello" (Leaf 3) (Bin "What's up?" (Leaf 4) (Leaf 5) we construct instances in lowercase:

BL $ \leaf bin -> bin "Hello" (leaf 3) (bin "What's up?" (leaf 4) (leaf 5)

The isomorphism is thus very easy one way: binleafFromBL f = runBL f Leaf Bin. The other side has a case dispatch, but is not too bad.

What about recursive algorithms on the recursive data? This is where it gets magical: foldr and runBL of Church encoding have both run whatever our functions were on the subtrees before we get to the trees themselves. Suppose for example that we want to emulate this function:

sumAnnotate :: (Num n) => BinLeaf a n -> BinLeaf (n, a) n
sumAnnotate (Leaf n) = Leaf n
sumAnnotate (Bin a x y) = Bin (getn x' + getn y', a) x' y' 
    where x' = sumAnnotate x
          y' = sumAnnotate y
          getn (Leaf n) = n
          getn (Bin (n, _) _ _) = n

What do we have to do?

-- pseudo-constructors for BL a x.
makeLeaf :: x -> BL a x
makeLeaf x = BL $ \leaf _ -> leaf x

makeBin :: a -> BL a x -> BL a x -> BL a x
makeBin a l r = BL $ \leaf bin -> bin a (runBL l leaf bin) (runBL r leaf bin)

-- actual function
sumAnnotate' :: (Num n) => BL a n -> BL n n
sumAnnotate' f = runBL f makeLeaf (\a x y -> makeBin (getn x + getn y, a) x y) where
    getn t = runBL t id (\n _ _ -> n)

We pass in a function \a x y -> ... :: (Num n) => a -> BL (n, a) n -> BL (n, a) n -> BL (n, a) n. Notice that the two "arguments" are of the same type as the "output" here. With Church encoding, we have to program as if we've already succeeded -- a discipline called "wishful thinking".

The Church encoding for the Free monad

The Free monad has normal form

data Free f x = Pure x | Roll f (Free f x)

and our Church encoding procedure says that this becomes:

newtype Fr f x = Fr {runFr :: forall z. (x -> z) -> (f z -> z) -> z}

Your function

matchFree p _ (Pure x) = p x
matchFree _ f (Free x) = f x

becomes simply

matchFree' p f fr = runFr fr p f
Rhizomorphous answered 14/7, 2015 at 21:50 Comment(0)
A
5

Let me describe the difference for a simpler scenario - lists. Let's focus on how one can consume lists:

  • By a catamorphism, which essentially means that we can express it using

    foldr :: (a -> r -> r) -> r -> [a] -> r
    

    As we can see, the folding functions never get hold of the list tail, only its processed value.

  • By pattern matching we can do somewhat more, in particular we can construct a generalized fold of type

    foldrGen :: (a -> [a] -> r) -> r -> [a] -> r
    

    It's easy to see that one can express foldr using foldrGen. However, as foldrGen isn't recursive, this expression involves recursion.

  • To generalize both concepts, we can introduce

    foldrPara :: (a -> ([a], r) -> r) -> r -> [a] -> r
    

    which gives the consuming function even more power: Both the reduced value of the tail, as well as the tail itself. Clearly this is more generic than both previous ones. This corresponds to a paramorphism which “eats its argument and keeps it too”.

But it's also possible to do it the other way round. Even though paramorphisms are more general, they can be expressed using catamorphisms (at some overhead cost) by re-creating the original structure on the way:

foldrPara :: (a -> ([a], r) -> r) -> r -> [a] -> r
foldrPara f z = snd . foldr f' ([], z)
  where
    f' x t@(xs, r) = (x : xs, f x t)

Now Church-encoded data structures encode the catamorphism pattern, for lists it's everything that can be constructed using foldr:

newtype List a = L (forall r . r -> (a -> r -> r) -> r)

nil :: List a
nil = L $ \n _ -> n

cons :: a -> List a -> List a
cons x (L xs) = L $ \n c -> c x (xs n c)

fromL :: List a -> [a]
fromL (L f) = f [] (:)

toL :: [a] -> List a
toL xs = L (\n c -> foldr c n xs)

In order to see the sub-lists, we have take the same approach: re-create them on the way:

foldrParaL :: (a -> (List a, r) -> r) -> r -> List a -> r
foldrParaL f z (L l) = snd $ l (nil, z) f'
  where
    f' x t@(xs, r) = (x `cons` xs, f x t)

This applies generally to Church-encoded data structures, like to the encoded free monad. They express catamorphisms, that is folding without seeing the parts of the structure, only with the recursive results. To get hold of sub-structures during the process, we need to recreate them on the way.

Apodosis answered 14/7, 2015 at 21:0 Comment(0)
C
4

Your

matchF
  :: Functor f
  => (a -> r)
  -> (f (F f a) -> r)
  -> F f a
  -> r

looks like the Scott-encoded Free monad. The Church-encoded version is just

matchF
  :: Functor f
  => (a -> r)
  -> (f r -> r)
  -> F f a
  -> r
matchF kp kf f = runF f kp kf

Here are Church- and Scott-encoded lists for comparison:

newtype Church a = Church { runChurch :: forall r. (a -> r       -> r) -> r -> r }
newtype Scott  a = Scott  { runScott  :: forall r. (a -> Scott a -> r) -> r -> r }
Compote answered 14/7, 2015 at 20:18 Comment(0)
S
2

It's a bit of a nasty one. This problem is a more general version of a puzzle everyone struggles with the first time they're exposed to it: defining the predecessor of a natural number encoded as a Church numeral (think: Nat ~ Free Id ()).

I've split my module into a lot of intermediate definitions to highlight the solution's structure. I've also uploaded a self-contained gist for ease of use.

I start with nothing exciting: redefining F given that I don't have this package installed at the moment.

{-# LANGUAGE Rank2Types #-}
module MatchFree where

newtype F f a = F { runF :: forall r. (a -> r) -> (f r -> r) -> r }

Now, even before considering pattern-matching, we can start by defining the counterpart of the usual datatype's constructors:

pureF :: a -> F f a
pureF a = F $ const . ($ a)

freeF :: Functor f => f (F f a) -> F f a
freeF f = F $ \ pr fr -> fr $ fmap (\ inner -> runF inner pr fr) f

Next, I'm introducing two types: Open and Close. Close is simply the F type but Open corresponds to having observed the content of an element of F f a: it's Either a pure a or an f (F f a).

type Open  f a = Either a (f (F f a))
type Close f a = F f a

As hinted by my hand-wavy description, these two types are actually equivalent and we can indeed write functions converting back and forth between them:

close :: Functor f => Open f a -> Close f a
close = either pureF freeF

open :: Functor f => Close f a -> Open f a
open f = runF f Left (Right . fmap close)

Now, we can come back to your problem and the course of action should be pretty clear: open the F f a and then apply either kp or kf depending on what we got. And it indeed works:

matchF
  :: Functor f
  => (a -> r)
  -> (f (F f a) -> r)
  -> F f a
  -> r
matchF kp kf = either kp kf . open

Coming back to the original comment about natural numbers: predecessor implemented using Church numeral is linear in the size of the natural number when we could reasonably expect a simple case analysis to be constant time. Well, just like for natural numbers, this case analysis is pretty expensive because, as show by the use of runF in the definition of open, the whole structure is traversed.

Subfusc answered 14/7, 2015 at 20:22 Comment(6)
"predecessor implemented using Church numeral is linear in the size of the natural number" — there is a trick (but split_fstream doesn't really deconstruct a list: zipping is still O(n^2) or maybe even worse, but you can zip infinite lists, i.e. the whole structure is not traversed).Compote
Thanks, that was interesting, but your open and close functions are similar to toF and fromF, and as I mentioned in the question, I already understand I can use them to solve the problem.Arillode
@Anupam Jain, they are quite different, since open and close are pure System F terms, while toF and fromF are not. I.e. gallais' solution doesn't leave the Church-encoded world, while your leaves. And splitting the structure (splitting — not converting to another (like with fromF)) is necessary, if you want to use functions with Scott-like type signatures (like your matchF) on Church-encoded data (like F).Compote
I guess it's a philosophical distinction then. Because your Open data type is exactly the definition of Free (except using Either instead of Free). Thanks for an informative answer though!Arillode
@Anupam Jain, Open is non-recursive, Free is recursive.Compote
Yep you are right! I glossed over the definition earlier.Arillode

© 2022 - 2024 — McMap. All rights reserved.